Many-valued logic

1920

The Polish logician and philosopher Jan Łukasiewicz began to create systems of many-valued logic in 1920, using a third value, "possible", to deal with Aristotle's paradox of the sea battle.

1921

Through this value it is possible to define a negation \underset{\Pi}{\neg} and an additional conjunction \underset{\Pi}{\wedge} as follows: \begin{align} \underset{\Pi}{\neg} u &:= u \xrightarrow[\Pi]{}\overline{0} \\ u \underset{\Pi}{\wedge} v &:= u\odot (u \xrightarrow[\Pi]{} v) \end{align} === Post logics Pm === In 1921 Post defined a family of logics P_m with (as in L_v and G_k) the truth values 0, \tfrac 1 {m-1}, \tfrac 2 {m-1}, \ldots, \tfrac {m-2} {m-1}, 1.

1922

In 1922 he developed a logic with infinitely many values L_\infty, in which the truth values spanned the real numbers in the interval [0,1].

1932

In 1932, Hans Reichenbach formulated a logic of many truth values where n→∞.

Kurt Gödel in 1932 showed that intuitionistic logic is not a finitely-many valued logic, and defined a system of Gödel logics intermediate between classical and intuitionistic logic; such logics are known as intermediate logics. == Examples == === Kleene (strong) and Priest logic === Kleene's "(strong) logic of indeterminacy" (sometimes K_3^S) and Priest's "logic of paradox" add a third "undefined" or "indeterminate" truth value .

The overdetermined truth value is here denoted as B and the underdetermined truth value as N. {| | || || || || || || |} === Gödel logics Gk and G∞ === In 1932 Gödel defined a family G_k of many-valued logics, with finitely many truth values 0, \tfrac 1 {k-1}, \tfrac 2 {k-1}, \ldots, \tfrac {k-2} {k-1}, 1, for example G_3 has the truth values 0, \tfrac 1 2, 1 and G_4 has 0, \tfrac 1 3, \tfrac 2 3, 1.

1951

Negation \underset{P}{\neg} and conjunction \underset{P}{\wedge} and disjunction \underset{P}{\vee} are defined as follows: \begin{align} \underset{P}{\neg} u &:= \begin{cases} 1, & \text{if }u=0\\ u-\frac {1}{m-1}, & \text{if }u\not= 0 \end{cases} \\ u \underset{P}{\wedge} v &:= \min\{u,v\} \\ u \underset{P}{\vee} v &:= \max\{u,v\} \end{align} === Rose logics === In 1951, Alan Rose defined another family of logics for systems whose truth-values form lattices.

123, December 1951, pp. 152–165; source). == Semantics == === Matrix semantics (logical matrices) === See Logical matrix ==Relation to classical logic== Logics are usually systems intended to codify rules for preserving some semantic property of propositions across transformations.




All text is taken from Wikipedia. Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License .

Page generated on 2021-08-05